Skip to main content

Abstract

This chapter offers a concise discussion of classic utilitarianism which is the prototypical moral doctrine of the utilitarian family. It starts with an analysis of the classic utilitarian criterion of rightness, gives an overview over its virtues and vices, and suggests an overall assessment of its adequacy as a theory of morality. Furthermore, it briefly discusses whether classic utilitarianism holds promise as a philosophy for doing business.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Note that the term “classic utilitarianism” does not refer to the doctrines held by classic utilitarians (Bentham, Mill and Sidgwick). It refers, rather, to a stylized moral system which involves paradigmatic elements of utilitarian moral philosophy.

  2. 2.

    This incompleteness may not be found problematic, as the following example shows: “Jones is driving through a tunnel behind a slow-moving truck. It is illegal to change lanes in the tunnel, and Jones’s doing so would disrupt the traffic. Nevertheless, she is going to change lanes (…). If she changes lanes without accelerating, traffic will be disrupted more severely than if she accelerates. If she accelerates without changing lanes, her car will collide with the back of a truck” [46]. Eric Carlson has pointed out that in this situation the act of (not) changing lanes arguably lacks moral status. The best Jones can do is not to change lanes and not to accelerate. So, if Jones does not accelerate, it is right for her not to change lanes. However, if she accelerates, it is right for her to change lanes, because if she does not, she will crash into the truck in front of her. In and of itself, it is therefore unclear whether the act of (not) changing lanes is right or wrong.

  3. 3.

    Note that this point about interpersonal comparison is confined to hedonism which supposes that “utility” has an objective referent. Modern-day economics has dropped this assumption and has developed ways of comparing utilities, for example, on the basis of a scaling procedure: “It is, of course, possible to define a metric on utility characteristics so that each person’s utility scale is coordinated with everyone else’s in a way that equal social importance is simply ‘scaled’ as equal marginal utility. If interpersonal comparisons of utility are taken to have no descriptive content, then this can indeed be thought to be a natural approach” [37].

  4. 4.

    This suggestion combines two ideas. I take from Rawls the idea of a “constrained utilitarianism” which maximizes utility within certain bounds ([2], p. 281). And I use Homann’s idea that the legal framework is to be used to ensure moral standards (cf. e.g. [51]).

  5. 5.

    I would like to thank Johanna Grießhammer, Ludwig Heider, Benjamin Hensel, Lisa Herzog, Christoph Lütge, and Martin Rechenauer for their useful comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

  1. Feldman F (1997) Utilitarianism, hedonism, and desert: essays in moral philosophy. CUP, Cambridge, p 13, emphasis in the original

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  3. Schroth J (2008) Distributive justice and welfarism in utilitarianism. Inquiry 51(2):123–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Mill JS, Bentham J, Austin J, Warnock M (2003) Utilitarianism: and, on liberty: including Mill’s essay on Bentham’ and selections from the writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, p 233

    Google Scholar 

  5. Sidgwick H (1907/1981) The methods of ethics. Hackett, Indianapolis

    Google Scholar 

  6. Korsgaard CM (1993) The reasons we can share: an attack on the distinction between agent-relative and agent-neutral values. Soc Philos Policy 10(1):24–51, emphasis in the original

    Google Scholar 

  7. Foot P (1985) Utilitarianism and the virtues. Mind 94(374):196–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Scheffler S (1985) Agent-centred restrictions, rationality and the virtues. Mind? 94(375):409–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Scheffler S (1982/1994) The Rejection of consequentialism: a philosophical investigation of the considerations underlying rival moral conceptions. OUP, Oxford, pp 2–3

    Google Scholar 

  10. Crisp P (2008) Well-being. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=well-being

  11. Mill JS (1863) Utilitarianism. Parker, Son and Bourn, London, pp 51–52

    Google Scholar 

  12. Sumner LW (1987) The moral foundation of rights. OUP, Oxford, p 171

    Google Scholar 

  13. Jollimore T (2011) Impartiality. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=impartiality

  14. Bykvist K (2009) Utilitarianism: a guide for the perplexed. Continuum, London

    Google Scholar 

  15. Mill, Utilitarianism, 37

    Google Scholar 

  16. Slote MA (1985) Utilitarianism, moral dilemmas, and moral cost. Am Philos Q 22(2):161–168

    Google Scholar 

  17. Norcross A (1995) Should utilitarianism accommodate moral dilemmas? Philos Stud 79:59–83

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Kagan S (1998) Normative ethics. Westview, Colorado, p 17

    Google Scholar 

  19. Foot P (1978) Virtues and vices and other essays in moral philosophy. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 19–32

    Google Scholar 

  20. Thomson JJ (1985) The trolley problem. Yale Law J 94(6):1395–1415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Scanlon TM (1999) What we owe to each other. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  22. Griffin J (1988) Well-being: its meaning, measurement and moral importance. OUP, Oxford, p 154

    Google Scholar 

  23. Vallentyne P (2006) Against maximizing act-consequentialism. In: Dreier JL (ed) Contemporary debates in moral theory. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, pp 21–37

    Google Scholar 

  24. Wallace RJ (2009) Practical reason. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=practical-reason

  25. Nida-Rümelin J (2001) Strukturelle Rationalität. Reclam, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  26. Kagan S (1994) Defending options. Ethics 104(2):333–351

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Slote MA (1984) Morality and the self-other asymmetry. J Philos 81(4):179–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Moore GE (1988) Principia ethica. Prometheus Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  29. Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state, and utopia. Basic Books, New York, pp 42–45

    Google Scholar 

  30. Scanlon TM (1975) Preference and urgency. J Philos 72(19):655–669

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Sen AK (1985) Well-being, agency and freedom: the Dewey lectures 1984. J Philos 82(4):169–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Popper KR (1945/2008) The open society and its enemies: the spell of Plato. Routledge, New York, p 317

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sen AK, Foster JE (1973) On economic inequality. OUP, Oxford, p 16

    Book  Google Scholar 

  34. Parfit D (1986) Reasons and persons. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Sinnott-Armstrong W (2008) Consequentialism. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=consequentialism

  36. Williams BAO (1982) Persons, character and morality. In: Williams BAO (ed) Moral luck: philosophical papers, 1973–1980. CUP, Cambridge, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  37. Sen AK (1997) Equality of what? In: Sen AK (ed) Choice, welfare and measurement. HUP, Cambridge, MA, pp 353–370

    Google Scholar 

  38. Jeske D (2008) Special obligations. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=special-obligations

  39. Hooker B (2003) Ideal code, real world. OUP, Oxford, p 64

    Google Scholar 

  40. Parfit D (2003) Equality and priority. In: Matravers D, Pike JE (eds) Debates in contemporary political philosophy: an anthology. Routledge, London, pp 115–132

    Google Scholar 

  41. Bergström L (1966) The alternatives and consequences of actions: an essay on certain fundamental notions in teleological ethics. Almqvist & Wiksell, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  42. Castaneda H-N (1968) A problem for utilitarianism. Analysis 28(4):141–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Bykvist K (2002) Alternative actions and the spirit of consequentialism. Philos Stud 107(1):45–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Carlson E (1999) Consequentialism, alternatives, and actualism. Philos Stud 96:253–268

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Feldman F (1986) Doing the best we can: an essay in informal deontic logic. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  46. Goldman HS (1978) Doing the best one can. In: Goldman AI, Kim J (eds) Values and morals: essays in honor of William Frankena, Charles Stevenson, and Richard Brandt. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 185–214

    Google Scholar 

  47. Smart JJC, Williams BAO (1973) Utilitarianism: for and against. CUP, Cambridge, p 137

    Google Scholar 

  48. Bentham J (1838) The collected works of Jeremy Bentham, published under the superintendence of his exectutor John Bowring, vol 1. Williams Tait, Edinburgh, p 16

    Google Scholar 

  49. Sen AK (1980–1981) Plural utility. Proc Aristotelian Soc 81:193–215

    Google Scholar 

  50. Dinwiddy JR, Twining WL (2004) Bentham: selected writings of John Dinwiddy. SUP, Stanford, p 49

    Google Scholar 

  51. Homann K, Luetge C (2004) Einführung in die Wirtschaftsethik. LIT, Münster

    Google Scholar 

  52. Snoeyenbos M, Humber J (2002) Utilitarianism and business ethics. In: Frederick R (ed) A companion to business ethics. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, pp 17–29

    Google Scholar 

  53. Rawls J (1993/1996) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York, p 269

    Google Scholar 

  54. Smart JJC, Williams BAO (1973) Utilitarianism: for and against. CUP, Cambridge, p 150

    Google Scholar 

  55. Kagan S (1989) The limits of morality. OUP, Oxford, p 17

    Google Scholar 

  56. Sen AK (2010) The idea of justice. Penguin, London, p 282

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nikil Mukerji .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this entry

Cite this entry

Mukerji, N. (2013). Utilitarianism. In: Luetge, C. (eds) Handbook of the Philosophical Foundations of Business Ethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1494-6_27

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1494-6_27

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-1493-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-1494-6

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics